Home » Islam » Islamic Philosophy » The Problem of Contradiction in Islamic Philosophy
  Services
   About Us
   Islamic Sites
   Special Occasions
   Audio Channel
   Weather (Mashhad)
   Islamic World News Sites
   Yellow Pages (Mashhad)
   Kids
   Souvenir Album
  Search


The Problem of Contradiction in Islamic Philosophy

By: Ayatullah Shaheed Murtadha Mutahhari
We have already considered Hegel's concept of the reconciliation of the contradictory concepts of being and non‑being in becoming. Now, we shall turn our attention to the treatment this subject receives in Islamic philosophy. There are numerous references to this topic by Muslim thinkers.
Fakhr al‑Din al‑Razi has a famous paradox concerning the problem of becoming. He believed that gradual emergence of things is meaningless. All the things that we think emerge gradually, are in fact born in a sudden manner. The illusion of gradual emergence of a thing is caused by the fact that the object in question is made up of a number of parts. As each part emerges suddenly and these emergences follow one another in succession, we are deluded into thinking that we are witnessing the emergence of one whole object, while in reality we are wit­nessing the creation of a number of things, each of which is born quite spontaneously; each part being quite separate and independent of the anterior and posterior parts. From this analysis, al‑Razi concludes that all movements are in fact a combination of independent parts none of which is a movement and gradual emergence from potentiality into actuality.
Al‑Razi defends his position in the following manner. Anything that does not exist and then comes into being, its being must have a beginning. Furthermore, this beginning is simple and indivisible. It has no beginning, middle, or end. If the beginning had a beginning, middle, and end, then the real beginning would be the beginning of the begin­ning, and its middle and end would cease to be the part of begin­ning. We apply the same argument to the new beginning; if it were not simple the same difficulty would arise. Therefore, we are forced to conclude that beginning is simple and indivisible.
Next we say, anything that comes into being, must either be in a state of existence at its beginning or in a state of non‑existence. If we say that a thing was in the state of non‑being at the beginning of its
existence, then we cannot say that it was at the beginning of its exis­tence; rather, we must say that it was in the state of non being and is still in the state of non being. It would be impossible to say that such an object is in the beginning of existence. We are forced to conclude that a thing exists at the beginning of its being.
Now, either something of that object remains to come into being or it does not. If nothing remains to come into being, then we have admitted that the thing in question was fully and completely existent at the beginning of its being. Since the beginning is simple and indivisible, the object in question must have come into existence suddenly not gradually. If some of the object still remains, the question arises: is the thing remaining which did not exist at the beginning of the existence of the object, identical with that which existed at the beginning, or, are they two different things? It is impossible for them to be identical because a particular thing cannot both be and not be at one and the same time. If on the other hand, the thing remaining which is to come into being is different from that which has come into being, then that which came into being in the beginning has come into being fully and instantaneously and nothing of it remains to emerge later. The thing which is yet to come into being, then, is something completely diffe­rent, distinct and independent of what has already come into being. Gradual emergence and `becoming,' then, are meaningless notions.
The views expressed by al‑Razi caused a great stir among the Muslim thinkers and led to renewed efforts to better understand the nature of movement and time. The theory of time as the fourth dimen­sion of matter, which was forwarded in the Muslim world by Sadr al­ Din Shirazi (Mulla Sadra), came in the wake of these intense philoso­phic efforts.
Mir Damad is the first Muslim thinker to have solved properly the problems raised by Fakhr al Din al‑Razi. Mir Damad first tackles the problem of beginning. He says that when we talk of a gradually emerging object having a beginning, this does not mean that the object in ques­tion came into being instantaneously and then continued its existence so that some instant should be taken as the starting point of its being. Such a beginning is appropriate for things which come into existence suddenly and instantaneously, not to gradually emerging things.
Beginning in the gradually emerging things means that since the thing that comes into being has extension and dimensions, which in turn corresponds to a temporal dimension, its being possesses the dimension of time, and since its existence is finite, it must have two ends, each end corresponding to a hypothetical point in time. One of these points is its beginning and the other is its end. Therefore the beginning and the end of the gradually emerging object both exist in the instant and not in time. The extremities i.e. the beginning and the end of a continuous entity, whether spatial or temporal, can never be considered as parts of that entity. So the question whether the end points of a continuum are simple or not does not arise. For example, the end point of a line is not part of the line. In fact, the limit of any extended thing has no exis­tence of its own; it is a concept abstracted from the limitation of being. The instant is also nothing but a hypothetical point in time.
Mir Damad then turns his attention to the ontological mode of the temporal and gradually emerging entities and probes into the nature of time itself. He claims that because this kind of objects are existential­ly weak, the stages of being and non‑being are mixed in them. Every stage of their being is associated with the non‑being of another stage. Therefore, the answer to the question raised by Fakhr al‑Din al‑Razi that if a part of a gradually emerging thing becomes existent while another part is still non‑existent, does the object in question exist or not, is that every part of that object exists in a particular segment of time. And in another segment of time where another part of the object exists, the first part is non‑existent. The totality of the object as a wholly complete unit exists in the totality of time and not in any par­ticular segment of it, and not in any instant.
In his book al Asfar, Mulla Sadra expresses the same view in a more forceful manner. In the eleventh chapter of his book (the chapter dealing with potentiality and actuality), he says: Movement and time are among those things which are existentially weak, i.e. things in which being and non‑being are interwoven. Their actuality is asso­ciated with their potentiality, and their coming into being is the same as their annihilation. The existence of every part necessitates the annihilation of some other part, or rather, it is none other than the non‑being of some other part.
Discussing the relationship of the changing to the unchanging in chapter twenty‑one of the discussion on "potentiality and actuality", he first says: "The kinds of actuality and stability that various objects possess are different from one another, and the Ultimate Source has given every object the distinctive form of stability peculiar to itself. And, whenever the stability which an object has is the stability of change, and the actuality of it is the realization of its potentiality and power, inevitably, that would be the sort of stability and actuality which would be granted to it."
Mulla Sadra continues his discussion by saying: The thing whose perpetuation or continuity is identical with its becoming ever new is nature. And the thing whose actuality is identical with absolute potentiality, is the primordial, formless matter. And that thing whose unity is identical with its actual multiplicity is the number. And the thing whose actual unity is identical with its potential multiplicity is the body and its physical properties.
In the twenty‑eighth chapter of the discussion on potentiality and actuality, Mulla Sadra draws a delicate inference from verse 61 of the sixth chapter of the Holy Quran which is as follows: And He is the Supreme, above His servants, and He sends keepers over you; until when death comes to one of you, Our messengers cause him to die, and they are not remiss.
The inference that Sadr al‑Din Shirazi draws from the above quoted verse is this: "A thing, the being and non‑being of which are intermixed, and its mere persistence and continuity entails its destruc­tion and annihilation, inevitably, the means of its continued existence are identical with the causes of its destruction and annihilation. There­fore, in the Quranic verse the same entities that have the duty of guard­ing the individual are entrusted with the duty of bringing about his death and oblivion, when the time for it comes. In other words, the agents of survival and preservation of life are transformed in time into the agents of death and decay."
How is it that such thinkers who so explicitly defend the view that being and non‑being are united and intermixed in the natural world, still defend the validity of the Law of Contradiction and call it umm al­ qadaya, or "the mother of all theorems"?
The fact of the matter is that in the view of these philosophers, the interwovenness of being and non‑being, which is a necessary charac­teristic of all changing and transitory things, in no way negates the validity of the Principle of Contradiction. In their view, the difficulty has been caused by failing to distinguish between the various ways in which we perceive non‑being. In other words, the problem is caused by a failure to adequately understand the mind's tendency to distort and miscomprehend the meaning of nonexistence.
In order to comprehend this matter properly, two things must be kept in mind:
(a) It is well‑known that logicians divide propositions into two general categories of affirmative and negative propositions. In the case of the affirmative propositions, the judgement of the mind is clear: that is, our mind either affirms the existence of the subject of the proposi­tion or its having a particular predicate or property, as, for example, in such statements as "John is", or, "John is standing."
Now, how about the negative propositions? For example, if we say, "John is not standing", what is the purport of this proposition? and what is the mental process involved in reaching a conclusion about it? At first, we might think that the purport of this proposition is that, John is in a non‑standing position. Such an inference is certainly false. "John is non‑standing " is an affirmative proposition. That is, its essence and nature is affirmative. The negation in the proposition is made a part of the predicate and it is called an `affirmative proposition with a diverted predicate.' Whether a proposition is negative or affirma­tive cannot be determined by its subject or predicate. It is a question the answer to which must be sought beyond the subject and the predi­cate. Failure to make distinction between these two can cause nume­rous errors in the reasoning process and in making inferences. Of course, those who are familiar with logic do not mistake these two kinds of propositions with each other and there is no difference of opinion among logicians regarding this matter.
Those who consider the affirmation and negation in propositions to be beyond the scope of the subject and the predicate, belong to two different groups. One group believes that the difference between these two types of propositions is a question of "relationship": affirmative relationship and negative relationship. When we say, "John is standing", John and standing are related to each other with a copula which is of the kind that may be designated as "being". And when we say, "John is not standing", the relationship between them is of the "non‑being" kind. This group holds the view that the Persian words, ast (is) and nist (is not) represent the relationship between subject and predicate in a proposition.
However, another group which includes Ibn Sina and Mulla Sadra maintain that the "relationship explanation" is completely erroneous. In their opinion, the same sort of relationship and copula exists in both affirmative and negative propositions. And the kind of copula in both kinds of propositions is affirmative. Such an affirmation, however, is related to concepts (subject‑predicate terms) rather than to judgements. The difference between the affirmative and the negative propositions is that in the affirmative proposition the mind judges and affirms the existence of the relationship between the subject and the predicate in the external world, whereas in the negative proposition the existence of such a relationship is denied by the mind.
The purport of the negative proposition, therefore, is not that there exists in the external world a certain thing and that thing is a "relationship of non‑being" between the subject and the predicate.
What the negative proposition indicates is that the affirmative relation­ship which exists in the conceptual form in the mind does not exist externally. In other words, what is judged and affirmed in the affirma­tive propositions is the occurrence of the relationship in the external reality, while in negative propositions what is judged is the non‑exis­tence or the non‑occurrence of the same relationship. The affirmative proposition tells of the correspondence of the relationship with the external reality, while the negative proposition tells that such a corres­pondence does not occur. The view that has been expressed while defining declarative statements as opposed to non‑declarative ones that "if the truth or the falsehood of the relationship (between the subject and the predicate) can be ascertained through reference to the external reality, the statement is declarative, otherwise it is non‑declarative" and that this also applies to the negative propositions, is false.
In the view of these scholars, the content of the negative proposi­tion is salb al‑rabt (denial of a relation) and not rabt al‑salb (a negative relation). In other words, the content of the negative proposition is the negation of the affirmative relation, not the affirmation of the negative relation, which constitutes the content of an affirmative proposition with a diverted predicate (mujabat ma'dalat al‑muhmul).
The truly negative proposition is precisely as has just been des­cribed, and this is the only expression for the contradictory of exis­tence. The purport of the negative proposition is nothing other than the negation of the content of the affirmative proposition. Furthermore, the negative proposition does not assign any conditions to the act of negation itself, be they temporal or spatial. Whatever terms of specifi­cations that exist in the negative proposition are subject to negation and are part of the predicate which is being negated.
Only with this consideration could non‑being be said to exist as a contradiction and negation of being. To put it in another way, if we have two propositions one of which negates all the contents of the other and has no other function than this, then these two proposi­tions are contradictory. For example, if we say that "Ahmad is standing at such and such a place at such and such a time", its contradictory would be: "It is not the case that Ahmad is standing on such and such a place at such and such a time." If a thousand conditions and terms be added to the first proposition, the second proposition negates the first proposition with all its myriad of conditions and terms; and this is the real meaning of the logical axiom that the contradiction of everything is its negation (naqid kull shay' raf`uh). Such two propositions, the real and logical contradictions of each other, are mutually exclusive, and the law of the mutual exclusivity of the contradictories applies to them.
Non‑being, interpreted and used in this way which is, by the way, the main interpretation and use of this concept has no external reality and inherent existence of its own. It can be neither a subject nor a predicate. The dimensions of time and space do not apply to it; time and space are not a vehicle for non‑being; they belong to the particular object that it negates. Therefore, in the sense just mentioned, on­ being is pure negation. Here, the intellect is taking an overview of the world and concludes that a particular conceptual entity simply does not exist in the external reality, i.e. it has no denotation.
There is another interpretation of non‑being which is in reality a figurative one. In this interpretation, non‑being has a denotation and exists in time and space. It can be both a subject and a predicate. What we have in this case is that when the mind surveys the external world and perceives that a certain thing is not in it, it supposes that negation has taken the place of affirmation and that non‑being has occupied the place of being. In other words, when it perceives the absence of a particular object in a specific location, our mind imagines that its place is empty and its non‑being occupies it. Thus interpreted, non being comes to occupy its own space just as being does. It also comes to possess its own essence and the capacity to be either the subject or the predicate. Therefore, there is a difference between the propositions, "X does not exist in the world", and "X is non‑existent in the world". In the second proposition for the "non‑existence" of "X" in a particu­lar space in the external world is posited. Of course, we know that non‑being has no real denotation. Inevitably the existence of other things is figuratively taken to denote the non‑existence of the hypo­thetical object. It is because of this that it is said: every stage of being marks the annihilation of another stage.
Now that the two interpretations of non‑being have been consi­dered, it can be clearly perceived that in its fundamental interpretation and meaning non‑being has no independent and inherent existence of its own, being purely a negation and denial of being. In the second interpretation, non‑being is granted independent existence metaphorically; however, in this sense it is not the contradictory of being.
(b) Now let us consider the question of becoming. Becoming refers to the continuity, gradualness and the fluidity of being. A thing that comes about gradually, possesses a sort of extension and continuity which is parallel to time. In fact, the extension of time is none other than the extension of the continuous and gradual stages of existence which are sequentially related to each other in the relation of potency and act.
A quality of the extended thing is that while it possesses a con­tinuous and actual unity, the intellect is able to divide it into mathe­matical parts and segments. Since the extension in question is temporal and it has its roots in potentiality and actuality, inevitably, the hypo­thetical parts and segments precede or succeed one another with no possibility of existing simultaneously. Furthermore, since these seg­ments have no simultaneity, they are devoid of each other, they lack each other. To put it another way, since no two segments can exist in the same time‑frame, each part presupposes the non‑existence (accord­ing to the second interpretation) of the other part. Or we may say that in the duration of the preceding part "non‑existence' of the succeeding part is true, and in the duration of the following part "non‑existence" of the preceding part is true.
On the other hand, we know that these divisions are imaginary and hypothetical ones, not really disconnected and discrete parts. Further­more, every extended object is infinitely divisible by the mind, and this divisibility does not come to an end. Every segment can be divided into two smaller parts everyone of which is the "non‑being" of the other part. Each of these new parts can in turn be divided into smaller parts everyone of which is the "non‑being" of all the others. These parts can be divided into even smaller ones, and so on ad infinitum. It is therefore inevitable that segments and stages are posited on an infinite scale. Furthermore, as degrees and parts are conceived infinitely, it follows that non‑being is also posited infinitely because each part implies the non‑being of all the other parts. Since no end to division can be con­ceived, being and non‑being are so closely interwoven that it is impos­sible to imagine any boundary between them.
In objects with a gradual existence, we cannot find any stage in the existence which remains constant in a duration of time irrespective of its length. We cannot find any stage of the existence of an evolving object remaining fixed in any particular duration of time, irrespective of how small the duration in question happens to be. Every stage and section of the evolving object can be divided into past and present and into preceding and succeeding parts. Every one of the newly defined stages can in turn be divided into a past and a future, while any one of the new segments can be divided into a preceding and a succeeding section, and this process can be continued ad infinitum. What cannot be found anywhere here is now, that is, the duration of time lying between the past and the future. The past and the future are all there is, and every past is a combination of a future and a past, while every future is also a combination of a past and a future. Whatever exist is either preceding something or following something, and everything which is preceding is itself a combination of a preceding thing and a following thing, while everything which is following is itself made up of something which precedes and something that follows. Everything is made up of being and non‑being. Anything that exists contains both being and non‑being within itself, just as everything that does not exist is also complex, both of being and non‑being.
Evidently, when we speak of the intermixing of being and non­being, we are not talking about the mixing of two real elements. The kind of mixture we have in mind involves one real element (being) and one hypothetical element (non‑being). Inevitably such a mixture takes place in the mind and the imagination, not in the external world and the external reality. As far as the external and the real world is concerned, all there is, is an existence which is slippery and fluid in nature. There is nothing outside of such existence.
From what has been discussed, it can be clearly understood that non‑being taken to mean the negation of being has no external reality. Therefore, it would be meaningless to speak of its mixture with exis­tence. On the other hand, when non‑being is interpreted as having a sort of hypothetical existence and reality of its own, and the capacity to mix with being it does not contradict existence. The claim, therefore, that the union of being and non‑being in process and becoming is equivalent to a coupling of contradictions and reconcilement of opposites, and that it negates the Law of Contradiction, and further­more, that Hegelian dialectics has succeeded in disproving the validity of the Law of Contradiction, is caused by not having paid sufficiently close attention to the real meaning of the problem and the different interpretations of the concept of non‑being.
The truth of the matter is that it is impossible for someone to understand the real meaning of the Law of Contradiction and deny its validity. If someone were to make the sort of claim that has been just mentioned and interpret arbitrary metaphors as contradicting the Law of Contradiction, it must be taken more as a joke than a serious argu­ment. Such claims merely indicate an over‑abundant appetite for new ways of philosophizing.
Besides the Islamic philosophers who have been mentioned, it should be kept in mind that our mystics and poets exhibited dialectical thinking long before Hegel, and had discovered the very core of dialec­tical thought which is the compatibility of being and non‑being. It was one such poet who said: The man of reason speaks of being, While the mystic speaks of nothingness; In the midst of water and mud of being and nothingness, I both am and am not
Much the same idea is expressed in the following poem: Like the rays of light, Which are separate from the sun, And yet are not separate, The universe is a sign of God, And yet it is not God.
You all see your image in the mirror, Yet the image in the mirror Is both you and not you.
Wherever you look, You shall see the unveiling of the hidden witness How can one say where He is or where He is not?
The dervish, who is a king in the land of poverty, Is looked on as a beggar by the masses, But in reality is no beggar at all.
This nothingness which appears as being, Seems to have permanence in the eyes of you and I, But in reality it has no permanence at all.
Kindness and indifference given out by the Beloved as "warning"; Why is it? I don't know if it is justified or not.
Hegel himself had understood the fact that what he called `the compatibility of contradictions' is something other than that which is deemed impossible by all reasoning minds. In his Treatise on Dialectics, under the heading "Hegel and contradiction," Paul Foulquie says: In Hegel's view, the dialectical method, according to which, the idea (absolute form) is actualized in mind and nature, is based on contradiction. It should be kept in mind, however, that Hegel's dialectics do not completely reject the Principle of Contradiction, and between it and the old dialectics‑which considered the Principle of Contradiction its foundation‑there is no differen­ce in this regard ....Although Hegel appears to say the opposite, inwardly, like all other human beings, he accepts the Principle of Contradiction.
Furthermore, in his Treatise on Metaphysics, page 369, Paul Foulquie says: synthesis of contradictions is about apparent contradictions, not real ones. Hegel believed that whatever is regarded as truth by the human mind, will always remain true, and is wholly contained in the later synthesis. In Hegel's view, intellectual progress means that only those elements of science the falsity of which has been demonstrated, be rejected.
The difference of opinion that prevails between the Islamic philo­sophers and Western thinkers like Hegel regarding the problem of becoming is not limited to the conclusion that Western scholars have tried to draw regarding the union of contradictions. Although both of these modes of thought appear to reach similar conclusions in that they say `in becoming, being and non‑being are in an embrace,' the founda­tions and roots of these two modes of thought are completely different, and they have emerged from completely different origins.
From the point of view of Hegelian dialectics, "Every conception is a combination of relations. We are able to conceive something only when we can imagine its relationship to some other object and know their similarities and differences. Any conception devoid of relation­ships would be meaningless. This is what is meant by the dictum `pure existence is identical with nothingness.' The sort of being that is devoid of all attributes and relationships does exist, and is meaningless."
"The first triad of Hegel's philosophical system, which is also the most famous, is: being exists. This is the stage of thesis or affirma­tion. However being which is undefined and has an unspecified nature so that we cannot say it is this or that, is equal to non‑being or nothing­ness. Thus, following our affirmation it becomes necessary to negate it. Therefore, we say: being is not. This negation is itself negated, and we reach the third stage: that of synthesis. Thus we say that being is becoming." (Paul Foulquie's Treatise on Dialectics) In Hegel's view, therefore, pure being cannot be real, and being becomes a reality through synthesis with non‑being.
In the opinion of the Islamic philosophers, especially Mulla Sadra, what possesses reality is pure being, and the determined and manifested beings derive their reality from pure being. In the opinion of these thinkers, when being reaches its weakest point in the order of its descent, it takes on a fluid quality, mixes with non; being, and takes the form of becoming. This is precisely the opposite of Hegel's notion of being.

Copyright © 1998 - 2024 Imam Reza (A.S.) Network, All rights reserved.